© 2017 Simon’s Cat Limited |
< Flynn's Cat - Part 1
So the cat is watching a cursor move about on my laptop screen. Is how the cat solves the problem of figuring out what the cursor is, embedded inside her somewhere sandwiched between perceiving and the movement of her paw, or is it developed and made possible through her interactions with the cursor?
So the cat is watching a cursor move about on my laptop screen. Is how the cat solves the problem of figuring out what the cursor is, embedded inside her somewhere sandwiched between perceiving and the movement of her paw, or is it developed and made possible through her interactions with the cursor?
Even before this problem-solving task, how does the
cat go about categorising the world she perceives? Is she constrained or
limited by the body she inhabits? I perceive her as black and white, but
is that because in some way, I am physiologically equipped to perceive her as
black and white. The next door neighbour’s dog may perceive her differently.
If I twist the can opener around a tin of cat food, does she perceive this,
since she has no opposable thumbs to understand the concept of twisting, or
does she merely see me move the can? Is there a pre-given world for either of
us, or are both of us bringing it forth from our respective histories of
structural coupling with artefacts in the world, which will be markedly
different?
And if how she categorises differs from how I categorise then
presumably any competences which depend on categorisation such as memory will
differ between us as well.
Standard cognitive science is criticised for
relying on amodal symbols and algorithms that cannot acquire the
representational function that standard cognitive science assigns them. Meaning
must come from elsewhere, for example, the characteristics of the body and the
interactions with the world that the body affords. According to O’Regan &
Noe (2001), vision is constituted by exploring, not by the mere activation of
neural representations; Vision involves the interaction of the visual apparatus
and its environment. If the cat’s legs move in a running motion while she is
sleeping on her side, she is not running, even if her legs are making the
correct movements, as her feet are not making contact with the ground. They
also argue that perception depends on possession of sensorimotor knowledge, and
it is the skilful activity of the cat as a whole that allows her to perceive.
Her interactions with the cursor obey regularities known as sensorimotor
contingencies and her visual experience is the exercise of those sensorimotor
contingencies. In a similar manner, if I stroke her, my tactile experience is
the knowledge of sensorimotor contingencies associated with tactile
simulations. But what is the nature of this knowledge? It is a tacit knowledge,
where experience of objects in my environment creates expectations in my
nervous system. Is it a type of know-how or a set of skills I have
acquired that allow me to perceive – the set of movements and adjustments that
gather information particular to the shape, colour, texture and other visual
attributes of the cat. And what does it mean to exercise this sensorimotor
knowledge? Is it my potential to perform these actions that allows me to perceive
the cat? Do I actually need to move my eyes over her to reveal
sensorimotor knowledge, or does it mean that at some time in the past, I moved
my eyes relative to a cat in a way that created knowledge of sensorimotor
contingencies, and thus, my perceptual experience now, is the knowledge I
acquired from those previous actions. This throws up a problem. If knowledge
alone constitutes the perceptual experience, then the mind is again, akin to a
brain in a vat, with the sensorimotor contingencies represented in the brain.
While this theme does emphasise the importance of the body in perception, this
is only weakly different from traditional cognitive science. If on the other
hand, my eyes are firmly fixed on my laptop and I do not perform actions now, along
with sensorimotor knowledge, will I fail to perceive the cat? This might
certainly explain inattentional blindness.
It can certainly be argued that this form of
knowledge is know-how rather than symbolical – it requires a brain in a body to
acquire the skills, but can’t know-how be represented symbolically? Can’t the
brain in a vat encode the know-how? So, either I do not perceive the cat
unless I physically exercise my sensorimotor contingency knowledge, or if I do
not exercise this knowledge, my experiences of the cat rest on previously
stored knowledge in my brain, which is admittedly functional in nature, but
must at the same time, be represented in some way.
So traditional cognitive science and this
particular theme of embodiment directly compete with each other in their
interpretation of data. While computational models of vision from traditional
cognitive science assume an independent world, separate from the algorithms
that derive information from it, embodiment depends on what my body brings to
processing the world it encounters. But is there a better way to do cognition?
This is the subject of the next post…
Flynn's Cat - Part 3 >
Flynn's Cat - Part 3 >
References
O'Regan, J. and Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor
account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
24(05), pp.939-973.
No comments:
Post a Comment